Saturday 18 January 2014

What is pseudoscience in complementary and alternative medicine?


Overview


Pseudoscience exhibits the superficial appearance of science but lacks its substance. In the case of complementary and alternative medicine (CAM), pseudoscientific procedures appear to play by the rules of science but in fact do not. Pseudoscientific procedures rarely possess the crucial safeguards against confirmation bias that characterize the mature sciences. Instead they exhibit the tendency to seek evidence consistent with hypotheses and to deny, dismiss, and distort evidence that is not. As a consequence, pseudoscience leaves itself vulnerable to errors.




The distinction between science and pseudoscience is not absolute or clear-cut; some sciences engage in pseudoscientific practices, and vice versa. Nevertheless, as philosopher of science Mario Bunge and others have observed, numerous indicators, or warning signs, of pseudoscience can be pinpointed. It should be noted that these indicators do not prove the presence of a pseudoscience, but the more such indicators accompany a discipline, the more skeptical one should be of that discipline. In particular, there are ten warning signs of pseudoscience, all of which are relevant to certain CAM practices.




Key Warning Signs


Overuse of ad hoc hypotheses. An ad hoc hypothesis is an escape hatch or loophole that allows proponents of claims to discount negative results. Although developed sciences sometimes make use of ad hoc hypotheses, pseudosciences routinely invoke them as ploys to immunize their claims from refutation. For example, a proponent of a new form of meditation found to be ineffective in ten independent studies might maintain that all of these investigations were flawed because they were not conducted by the technique’s developer, who is the only person qualified to perform them.



Absence of self-correction. Sciences tend to change over time in response to new data; pseudosciences rarely do. For example, despite extensive scientific data showing that an herbal remedy is ineffective for severe depression, a practitioner might continue to insist that the treatment should be prescribed for this condition.



Focus on confirmation rather than refutation. As philosopher of
science Karl Popper observed, science progresses most efficiently when
investigators strive to disprove their claims rather than to prove them. In
contrast, pseudosciences tend to focus on confirming rather than disconfirming
instances. For example, when confronted with evidence that an initial positive
finding could not be replicated in five other investigations, a proponent of using
acupuncture to treat diabetes might focus exclusively on the
positive result, and ignore the replication failures.



Reversed burden of proof. In science, the onus of proof lies with
the proponent of a claim, not with skeptics. In contrast, pseudosciences tend to
place the burden
of proof on skeptics rather than on proponents. For example,
an advocate of using shark cartilage to treat cancer might insist that critics
have not proven conclusively that shark cartilage is ineffective. In science, it
is up to the advocate to show that shark cartilage works, not up to the critic to
show that it does not.



Evasion of peer review. Sciences rely on a procedure called peer review, in which journal manuscripts reporting original findings are sent to several independent scholars to evaluate the merits of the studies. Many, if not most, manuscripts submitted to premier journals are rejected for publication; others are accepted only after multiple rounds of substantial revision. Although peer review is not a perfect process, it weeds out many errors in researchers’ methodology or conclusions. Some pseudoscientific CAM procedures circumvent the peer review process, thereby bypassing one of the key safeguards of science. For example, many advocates of energy therapies for anxiety disorders have advanced claims that have not been subjected to independent scrutiny by other scholars.



Mantra of holism. Many pseudosciences invoke the mantra of
holism; that is, they argue that a claim cannot be tested in isolation and must be
tested only in the context of all other claims. Holism is invoked to insulate
assertions against refutation. For example, a believer in naturopathy
might insist that a study showing that naturopathy is ineffective be dismissed
because persons who use naturopathy almost always do so along with other
treatments.



Over-reliance on anecdotal evidence. A familiar saying in science
is that “the plural of anecdote is not fact.” Anecdotes, which usually take the
form of “I know a person who” stories, can be helpful in science, especially when
they suggest fruitful hypotheses that can later be tested in rigorous
investigations. However, anecdotes rarely, if ever, justify a definitive claim
that a CAM technique works. For example, a practitioner who asserts that
homeopathy must be effective because he or she has witnessed
several persons “get better after receiving homeopathic remedies” is operating in
a pseudoscientific fashion.



Absence of boundary conditions. Pace University psychologist
Terence Hines noted that almost all scientific procedures possess boundary
conditions: limitations on when the technique works and when it does not work. In
contrast, pseudoscientific treatments frequently lack boundary conditions. Their
proponents often maintain that they are effective for virtually every condition
and every person. For example, an advocate of chiropractic
might contend that this method is effective not only for back problems but also
for cancer, multiple sclerosis, diabetes, and schizophrenia.



Use of scientific-sounding language. Many pseudosciences utilize scientific-sounding terms to create an aura of legitimacy. In doing so, however, they often use these terms incorrectly. For example, in explaining how their methods seem to work, they may refer to “quantum fields,” “neural networks,” or “complexity theory” yet also may strip these terms of much of their accurate meaning.



Absence of connectivity. In science, new ideas tend to build on, or connect with, earlier ideas. In contrast, many pseudosciences purport to construct entirely new paradigms from whole cloth. For example, the developer of a new magnet therapy might insist that his treatment relies on entirely undiscovered electromagnetic principles.




Conclusion

These ten warning signs of pseudoscience are not exhaustive. Social work researchers Bruce Thyer and Monica Pignotti have identified other features of pseudoscience, including a tendency to make extraordinary claims that go far beyond scientific evidence (such as claims of miracle cures), insistence that a technique is being unfairly suppressed by establishment scientists, and requirements that practitioners of the technique agree to vows of secrecy. In all cases, pseudosciences purport to be something they are not. Therefore, consumers should be wary of CAM procedures that display any of the warning signs presented here.


Pseudoscientific practices in health care may or may not be physically harmful in and of themselves, but they can be dangerous in other ways. Followers of CAM pseudoscience may avoid mainstream therapies or treatments and thereby fail to prevent or cure otherwise treatable conditions. Widespread adoption of ineffective methods can have a negative effect on public health, as in the case of parents who refuse to vaccinate their children over pseudoscientific fears that vaccination causes autism. Indoctrination in pseudoscience may also be harmful to the scientific community, as it undermines the viewpoints of legitimate scientists, distracts from scientific progress and the value of the scientific method, and disrupts scientific education. Finally, adhering to pseudoscientific beliefs can be expensive and time consuming as practitioners often seek to profit from their ideas and may require complex commitments from their followers. Although sometimes pseudoscientific CAM practitioners may honestly believe in the efficacy of their ideas, the field is also a common target for con artists and unscrupulous business seeking to exploit consumers' willingness to try and believe in new treatments.




Bibliography


Bausell, R. Barker. Snake Oil Science: The Truth About Complementary and Alternative Medicine. New York: Oxford University Press, 2007. Print.



Bunge, Mario. “What Is Pseudoscience?” Skeptical Inquirer 9 (1984): 36-46. Print.



Ernst, E. Healing, Hype, or Harm? A Critical Analysis of Complementary or Alternative Medicine. Exeter: Societas, 2008. Print.



Lilienfeld, Scott O., Steven J. Lynn, and Jeffrey M. Lohr, eds. Science and Pseudoscience in Clinical Psychology. New York: Guilford Press, 2003. Print.



Pigliucci, Massimo, and Boudry, Maarten. "The Dangers of Pseudoscience." New York Times. New York Times, 10 Oct. 2013. Web. 27 Jan. 2016.



"Pseudoscience and Medical Quackery in New Zealand in Relation to Allergy." Auckland Allergy Clinic. Auckland Allergy Clinic, 2014. Web. 27 Jan. 2016.



Saunders, Russell. "Warning: "Natural Medicine" is Often Code for "Pseudoscience." Daily Beast. Daily Beast, 3 Apr. 2014. Web. 27 Jan. 2016.

No comments:

Post a Comment

How can a 0.5 molal solution be less concentrated than a 0.5 molar solution?

The answer lies in the units being used. "Molar" refers to molarity, a unit of measurement that describes how many moles of a solu...